Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  174 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 174 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Horst Steinke

174

of simple truths» (V. Peckhaus,

Calculus Ratiocinator vs. Characteristica Universal-

is?

, cit., p. 182).

330

J. Hintikka,

Lingua universalis

, cit., p. 5.

331

Hintikka refers to it as «the possibility of

re

-interpreting language as

freely as interpreting [associating it to a scenario, actual or hypothetical] an

uninterpreted calculus» (

ibidem

).

332

S. Knuuttila,

Hintikka’s View of the History of Philosophy

, cit., p. 99; Hin-

tikka put it more quaintly (in terms of a (bygone) historical socioeconomic

setting): «[…] we are not tied to our language. Our language is our servant, we

are its masters. We can tell it what to do, and we are not committed to its do-

ing what it does in one way only. We can hire another one if one old language

does not serve us satisfactorily» (Id.,

Lingua universalis

, cit., p. 22).

333

Knuutttila (following Hintikka) illustrates this state of affairs by means

of Cubism: first of all, Cubism “stepped outside” thinking in terms of merely

finding a different visual (both pictorial and plastic) mode of representation of

reality, and re-thought, and re-discussed, the relation itself between represen-

tation and reality, thus making the language of art itself the object of language.

One of the concrete ways – but by no means the only one

this turned into

was a “model-theoretic” conception of perspective, that is, perspective itself

became an object of meta-discourse (Id.,

Hintikka’s Ideas About the History of

Ideas

, cit., pp. 118-119). For a multi-faceted discussion of Cubism in this con-

text, see J. Hintikka,

The Intentions of Intentionality and Other New Models for Modal-

ity

, Dordrecht-Boston, D. Reidel, 1975, pp. 223-251. For example, Hintikka’s

comments on Braque’s collages as confounding the relations between art and

reality, in effect, creating alternative (small-scale) “models” of reality (

ibid.

, p.

246). A similar observation is made by M. Piccolomini: «While they were chal-

lenging traditional art, they also challenged the meaning of art itself» (Id.,

Vico,

Sorel, and Modern Artistic Primitivism

, cit., pp. 123-130, p. 129).

334

When it comes to discussing philosophy of language, canonicity in-

volves inclusion of Wittgenstein in any discussion, regardless of whether it is

in a Vichian context or not. The former has been undertaken in E. Riverso,

Vico and Wittgenstein

, in

Giambattista Vico’s Science of Humanity

,

cit., pp. 263-273.

Riverso considers as the main commonality between the two thinkers, their

«reaction against abstract rationalism» (

ibid.

, pp. 264, 273). And, as noted

above, both would concur on rejecting the notion of calculus when it is un-

derstood as a purely formal(istic) operation. Other possible points of contact

between Vico and Wittgenstein are touched on in B. A. Haddock,

Vico and the

Problem of Historical Reconstruction

, in

Vico and Contemporary Thought

, cit., Part 1,

pp. 122-129, p. 128, and Id.,

Vico: The Problem of Interpretation

,

ibid.

, pp. 145-

162, p. 153. Of further interest is Riverso’s characterization of the essence of