Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  172 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 172 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Horst Steinke

172

principle of the “civic world”, language is not a part, however essential, of this

world, that is, it is not an institution alongside other institutions. The great

risk of conceiving it in this way is of understanding it as being a tool, and not

as autonomous)». See also

ibid.

, p. 284: «Il riconoscimento dell’autonomia del

linguaggio […] non resta privo di conseguenze per la filosofia (Recognition of

the autonomy of language is not without philosophical consequences)».

319

This is E. Coseriu’s view of Vico’s position in Id.,

Die Geschichte der

Sprachphilosophie von der Antike bis zur Gegenwart. Eine Übersicht. Teil

[

Part

]

II: Von

Leibniz bis Rousseau

, Tübingen, Gunter Narr Verlag, 1972, pp. 91-97.

320

The main references are J. Hintikka,

Lingua Universalis vs. Calculus Ratioc-

inator: An Ultimate Presupposition of Twentieth-Century Philosophy,

Dordrecht-

Boston-London, Kluwer Academic, 1997, and selected contributions in

The

Philosophy of Jaakko Hintikka

,

cit., including: S. Knuuttila,

Hintikka’s View of the

History of Philosophy

,

pp. 87-109; J. Hintikka,

Reply to Simo Knuuttila

, pp. 106-

112; G. Motzkin,

Hintikka’s Ideas about the History of Ideas

, pp. 113-131; H.

Sluga,

Jaakko Hintikka (And Others) on Truth

,

pp. 585-614; J. Hintikka,

Reply to

Hans Sluga

, pp. 615-624; M. Kusch,

Hintikka on Heidegger and the Universality of

Language,

pp. 713-729; J. Hintikka,

Reply to Martin Kusch

,

pp. 730-736. See also

M. Kusch,

Language as Calculus vs. Language as Universal Medium: A Study in Hus-

serl, Heidegger and Gadamer

, Dordrecht-Boston-London, Kluwer Academic,

1989, pp. 1-10.

321

With respect to the early modern period, L. Formigari noted: «For 17

th

and 18

th

century philosophers it had not been difficult to reconcile the univer-

sality of language with the variety of languages» (Id.,

A History of Language Phi-

losophies

, cit., p. 191).

322

According to V. Peckhaus, Leibniz does not use the term

lingua charac-

terica

(Id.,

Calculus Ratiocinator vs. Characteristica Universalis? The Two Traditions in

Logic Revisited,

in

Gottlob Frege: Critical Assessments of Leading Philosophers

, vol. 1,

ed. by M. Beaney and E. H. Reck, London-New York, Routledge, 2005, pp.

176-190, p. 179, footnote 41).

323

J. Hintikka,

Lingua universalis

, cit., p. IX: «Leibniz proposed […] a uni-

versal language of human thought whose symbolic structure would reflect di-

rectly the structure of the world of our concepts»; see also H. Sluga,

Jaakko

Hintikka (And Others) on Truth

, cit., pp. 587-588. Needless to say, this bears no

relationship to projects like the artificial language

Esperanto,

designed to re-

place natural languages as a common, “universal” means of communication.

The term “universal medium” arises also in other contexts, such as when art is

characterized, in its ubiquity, as the universal medium of personal/collective

expression. These, and other context-dependent, usages have in common

phenomenological approaches; we also include in this categorization Chom-