Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  235 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 235 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Vico’s Ring

235

ty”» (Id.,

Spinoza and History

, in

The Philosophy of Baruch Spinoza

, cit., pp. 171-

195, p. 186).

463

This epistemic direction in Spinoza’s hermeneutics (and scientific

thought, as discussed further below) is commented on by Sandys-Wunsch:

«One can see from Spinoza’s attempt [at biblical theology] that his concept of

what was philosophically true determined what he found to be significant or

not» (Id.,

Spinoza – the First Biblical Theologian

, cit., p. 339). By implication, the

supreme state of intuitive knowledge also, transitively, even affects, and is in-

separable from, the determination of the initial data generated by, and as, the

first kind of knowledge.

464

TTP

, p. 91.

465

Spinoza provides his examples of «those Scriptural pronouncements

which are concerned with moral conduct» in

TTP

, pp. 91-92.

466

Zac commented: «Le fond de la thèse que Spinoza défend dans le

Traité

théologico-politique

, c’est que l’Écriture nous prescrit l’obéissance et non la con-

naissance de l’essence de Dieu (The substance of the thesis that Spinoza de-

fends in the

Theological-Political Treatise

is that Scripture commands us obe-

dience, and not knowledge of the essence of God)» (Id.,

Spinoza et

l’interprétation de l’Écriture

, cit., p. 172). Similarly, C. Chalier: «Inutile en effet,

selon lui, d’étudier la Bible pour découvrir cette idée [l’idée adequate de Dieu]

car […] il soutient que si les “idées” de Moïse ou des prophètes relatives à

Dieu ont tel ou tel sens, elles ne sont jamais varies (It is useless, in fact, ac-

cording to him, to study the Bible in order to discover this idea [the adequate

idee of God] since […] he maintains that if the “ideas” of Moses or the

prophets about God have this or that meaning, they are never true)» (Id.,

Spi-

noza. Lecteur de Maïmonide. La question théologique-politique

, Paris, Les Éditions du

Cerf, 2006, pp. 66-67). On the other hand, the radical opposition intended

here between the second and third kind of knowledge, the “punch line”, is

not perceived by Morrison: «But he immediately contradicts this by saying

that Scripture “does not expressly teach as eternal doctrine” anything about

“what God is” or His providence and that “the prophets had disagreed

among themselves about these things”» (Id.,

Spinoza and History

, cit., p. 182).

This might be an opportune moment to underline Spinoza’s transparency in

relegating Scripture to a philosophically impertinent status by way of reference

to the history of biblical studies/criticism. C. Chalier,

Spinoza,

cit., p. 78, con-

cluded: «De son côté, Spinoza rejette ce langage [biblique] comme privé de

tout contenu philosophique […] (On his part, Spinoza rejects this [biblical]

language as devoid of all philosophical content […])». As pointed out above,

from a “model-theoretic” point of view, Spinoza rejected Meijer’s working

thesis that Scripture was an expression, a “model”, however flawed, of philo-