Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  231 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 231 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Vico’s Ring

231

442

In view of the fact that model theory has been particularly fruitful in

mathematics, the following example may be illustrative: The mathematician D.

Hilbert constructed an axiom system for Euclidean geometry (

Grundlagen der

Geometrie

, Leipzig, Teubner, 1899), leaving the notions of “point”, “line”, and

“plane” undefined; he then showed that it is possible to give concrete mean-

ing to these undefined fundamental concepts, and thus construct a

model

of

the axiomatic system by

interpreting

points, lines, and planes as pairs of real

numbers on the real number plane, subject to certain equations, thus making

the axiom system

true

in this interpretation (see A. B. Sossinsky,

Geometries

,

Providence, Rhode Island, American Mathematical Society, 2012, p. 6). The

model-theoretic perspective has not been limited to mathematics, however; it

has found application in cognitive psychology (see Ph. N. Johnson-Laird,

Mental models and human reasoning

, in «PNAS», 107, 2010, 43, pp. 18243-18250);

cultural anthropology (see M. Bang et al.,

Cultural mosaics and mental models of

nature

, in «PNAS», 104, 2007, 35, pp. 13868-13874).

While borrowing model-theoretic concepts and language for the present

discussion, the underlying concepts do not depend, however, on this particu-

lar terminology in whole or in part. For example, what we have called

model

,

has also been termed

universe of interpretation

, and the targeted state of affairs,

interpretable entities

(see D. Kayser,

Abstraction and natural language semantics

, in

«Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B», 2003, 358, pp. 1261-

1268, p. 1267). On a higher, philosophical level, the equivalent, not necessarily

isomorphic or coextensive, term for

model

might be

field of sense

(see M. Gabri-

el,

Is the world as such good? The question of theodicy

, in

Dimensions of Goodness

, ed. by

V. Hösle, Newcastle upon Tyne, Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2013, pp.

45-65, p. 53; see also Id.,

Warum es die Welt nicht gibt

, Berlin, Ullstein, 2013, pp.

91-96, for the German equivalent

Sinnfeld;

published in English as

Why the

World Does Not Exist

, trans. by G. S. Moss, Cambridge-Malden, Polity Press,

2015, as well as the extensive treatment in Id.,

Fields of Sense: A New Realist On-

tology

, Edinburgh, Edinburgh Univeristy Press, 2015; for the Italian equivalent

regione d’essere,

see M. Ferraris,

Manifesto del nuovo realismo

, Rome-Bari, Laterza,

2012, p. 71).

443

Walther points out: «Meyers Beweisziel im

Interpres

ist es […] in

kon-

struktiver

Absicht the Philosophie als einziges Kriterium […] der authentischen

Bedeutung der biblischen Texte […] als auch […] der Wahrheit der so ermit-

telten Aussagen zu erweisen […] (Meyer’s objective in

Interpres

is […] to

demonstrate,

constructively

, how philosophy proves to be the only criterion […]

of the authentic meaning of biblical texts […] as well as […] the truth of the

propositions arrived at in this manner)» (Id.,

Biblische Hermeneutik und historische

Erklärung

, cit., p. 239; italics original).