Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  56 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 56 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Horst Steinke

56

ICS,

in R. W. Shahan and J. I. Biro

(ed. by),

Spinoza: New Perspectives

, Norman,

University of Oklahoma Press, 1978, pp. 71-111. Lachterman described his

approach as follows: «The contours of Spinoza’s project stand out more

sharply when set alongside those works of his most prominent contemporar-

ies or near-predecessors» (

ibid.

, p. 74). Our goal is therefore strictly limited,

namely, only to make the “contours” of Vico’s geometrical method in the

“Elements” stand out, rather than to do full justice to one of the major works

of philosophy in history.

70

Historically, geometry of a fairly sophisticated kind was practiced long

before Euclid, but it were Greek philosopher-mathematicians who started to

cast it in a logico-deductive system, using such concepts as definitions, postu-

lates, axioms, theorems, corollaries, conclusions, proofs, etc. (For ancient

mathematics, see, for example, V. Katz

(ed. by),

The Mathematics of Egypt, Meso-

potamia, China, India, and Islam: A Sourcebook

,

Princeton-Oxford, Princeton

University Press, 2007; on the Greek achievement, see C. A. Wilson,

On the

Discovery of Deductive Science

, in «The St. John’s Review»

,

XXXI, 1980, 2, pp. 21-

31; for example, comparison of Babylonian and Greek mathematics motivated

the conclusion: «While Greek geometry was

abstract and reasoning

, Babylonian

geometry was

concrete and numerical

”, (J. Friberg,

A Remarkable Collection of Baby-

lonian Mathematical Texts

, in «Notices of the AMS [American Mathematical So-

ciety]», 55, 2008, 9 pp. 1076-1086, p. 1079; italics original). Thus, when refer-

ring to the “geometric method”, it is not geometry

per se

that is in view but the

logico-deductive approach in general; see also the same distinction made in

Th. C. Mark, “

Ordine Geometrica Demonstrata”: Spinoza’s Use of the Axiomatic

Method,

in «The Review of Metaphysics», 29, 1975, 2, pp. 263-286, pp. 264-

265).

While this is not the place for a closer look at the indispensable role that

logic and deduction play in mathematics, it still deserves mention that mathe-

matics cannot be absolutely equated to, or exhausted by, the application of

logic and deduction alone. See E. N. Giovannini,

Intuición y Método Axiomático

en la Concepción de la Geometría de David Hilbert

, in «Revista Latinoamericana de

Filosofía», XXXVII, 2011, 1, pp. 35-65; D. Babbitt - J. Goodstein,

Guido

Castelnuovo and Francesco Severi: Two Personalities, Two Letters

, in «Notices of the

AMS», 56, 2009, 7, pp. 800-808; referring to two leading contributors of the

Italian school of algebraic geometry in the late 1800’s and early 1900’s, stating:

«Castelnuovo was an unabashed champion of the role of intuition in the suc-

cess of the Italian school» (p. 801). More recently, the mathematician I. Stew-

art wrote: «Proofs are discovered by people, and research in mathematics is

not just a matter of step-by-step logic» (Id.,

Visions of Infinity: The Great Mathe-

matical Problems,

New York, Basic Books, 2013, p. 10).