Table of Contents Table of Contents
Previous Page  116 / 298 Next Page
Information
Show Menu
Previous Page 116 / 298 Next Page
Page Background

Horst Steinke

116

desired state. For further lexical information on the verb, see R. Ruggiero,

No-

va Scientia Tentatur

, cit., p. 141, footnote 1.

217

G. Cacciatore,

Un’ idea moderna di certezza

, cit., p. 195; A. Battistini,

Note

conclusive

, in

Vico nella storia della filologia

, cit., pp. 199-208, p. 206.

218

D. Ph. Verene summeds it up well: «What has been originally made by

human choice, a custom, a word, a law in the particular life of a people, must

be remade by an act of philosophical thought that shows how it embodies in

itself not just the conditions or history of that people but the universal princi-

ples of humanity» (Id.,

Imaginative Universals and Narrative Truth

, cit., p. 9).

219

For the original Italian see G. Vico,

La Scienza nuova

.

Le tre edizioni

, cit.,

p. 893; italics and capitalization in the original.

220

As already stated above, both functors are a

pair

, and in category-

theoretic language, they are

left-adjoint

and

right-adjoint

, according to their re-

spective direction. The sense of pairing is captured by N. Struever’s com-

pound expression of «philosophicalised philology and historicized philoso-

phy» (Id.,

Collingwood’s Vichianism

, in

Razionalità e modernità in Vico,

cit., pp. 317-

333, p. 331). Struever associates the first approach with Vico, the second with

Collingwood, while we find both approaches present in Vico.

We are therefore only in partial, qualified agreement with L. Pompa who

described Vico’s “logic” as follows: «The “ideal eternal history” is therefore a

theory about the nature and history of a possible society, deduced from a

network of mutually consistent, universal, and necessary synthetic proposi-

tions. The formulation of the categorical relationships which is assumed in the

statements of these propositions is the first part of the work of the philoso-

pher. This adducing of actual propositions, and the deduction of the theory

from them, is the second part of the work of the philosopher, i.e., the work of

the philosopher understood as a theoretical sociologist» (Id.,

Vico’s Science

, in

«History and Theory», 10, 1971, 1, pp. 49-83, p. 67; also appeared in Italian as

La scienza di Vico

, trans. by M. Donzelli, in «BCSV», II, 1972, pp. 13-51). We

can agree to denoting the

ideal eternal history

as a «theory», as the work of a

«theoretical sociologist», as well to the «formulation of the categorical rela-

tionships […] of the philosophers», however, the “adjunction” of mutually

interacting functors between “philosophy” and “philology” precludes any type

of straightforwardly “deductive” nexus. Pompa develops his thesis also in his

Vico: A Study of the “New Science”

, cit., pp. 73-111; Id.,

Hermenéutica Metafísica y

Metafísica Hermenéutica

, trans. by J. A. Marín-Casanova, in «CsV», 7-8, 1997, pp.

141-165.

221

According to Schaeffer, «the principle implicated in custom must be

exposed so that they may be altered or reaffirmed in a new praxis or in a

code» (Id.,

Vico’s Il diritto universale and Roman Law

, cit., p. 50). «The principles